The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Published Nov 25, 2021, 6:00 AM

Daniel talks to Sean Carroll about the quantum multiverse, and whether it is real

Learn more about your ad-choices at https://www.iheartpodcastnetwork.com

See omnystudio.com/listener for privacy information.

If you love iPhone, you'll love Apple Card. It's the credit card designed for iPhone. It gives you unlimited daily cash back that can earn four point four zero percent annual percentage yield. When you open a high Yield Savings account through Apple Card, apply for Apple Card in the wallet app subject to credit approval. Savings is available to Apple Card owners subject to eligibility. Apple Card and Savings by Goldman Sachs Bank USA, Salt Lake City Branch, Member FDIC terms and more at applecard dot com. When you pop a piece of cheese into your mouth, you're probably not thinking about the environmental impact. But the people in the dairy industry are. That's why they're working hard every day to find new ways to reduce waste, conserve natural resources, and drive down greenhouse gas emissions. How is US Dairy tackling greenhouse gases? Many farms use anaerobic digesters to turn the methane from manure into renewable energy that can power farms, towns, and electric cars. Visit US dairy dot COM's Last Sustainability to learn more.

Our iHeartRadio Music Festival for the Senate by Capital One. Coming back to Las Vegas September twenties at twenty first, A weekend full of superstar performances Hey Sap, Rocky Banks, Sean Camila, kabyl Tojika When, Stefani hol Keith Urban, New Kids on the Block, Paramore, Chaboozie, The Black Crows, The Weekend, Thomas Red, Victoria, Monette Hold Plays, Chris Martin and Moore, stream Live Holy on Hulu, and get It gets to be There at AXS dot com.

Hi everyone, it's me Katie Couric. You know, if you've been following me on social media, you know I love to cook, or at least try, especially alongside some of my favorite chefs and foodies like Benny Blanco, Jake Cohen, Lighty Hoyke, Alison Roman and Ina Garten. So I started a free newsletter called Good Taste to share recipes, tips and kitchen mustaves. Just sign up at Katie Couric dot com slash good Taste. That's k A T I E C O U r I C dot com Good Taste. I promise your taste buds will be happy you did.

What if your idea of how the universe works is just wrong? I mean, you live in a world that seems to make sense of you that seems to follow rules that you're familiar with. But what if that's just wrong? Could reality what's actually out there beyond our brains and our senses. Could it be something so strange and bizarre that we would hardly recognize it? Could it be dramatically different from the glimpses we get through our senses and experiments. There's a vital clue that might just point us in that direction, something that has puzzled physicists and philosophers for nearly one hundred years, and that may take another one hundred years to solve. Solving it might require us to swallow a picture of reality that is mind bendingly strange to our little human brains. Hi, I'm Daniel. I'm a particle physicist, and I'm drawn to the possibility that the universe might be very different from the way we imagine it. What is the goal of physics, anyway, if not to reveal the true nature of reality to us? We build mathematical stories in our minds and apply them to our experiences. But why Immediately It's because we want to predict what will happen when we throw a stone or jump a river. But going deeper it gives us the chance to ask questions about how the universe works. If our mathematical story describes the universe, then we can look at that math and ask why the universe seems to follow that and what it all means. And sometimes the universe out there seems to insist on a mathematical story that we find very weird, shocking, almost And that is the goal of physics, not just to give us the power to throw rocks and jump rivers, but to reveal the truth. And the most exciting moments are when the truth and our intuition clash dramatically, when the universe says to us, nuh uh, your ideas about the universe are just wrong. And that's the goal of this podcast. Daniel and Jorge Explain the Universe, a production of iHeartRadio in which we tackle the biggest and hardest and nastiest and funnest questions of the universe. The ones that make your brain twist, the ones that slip away from you just as you thought you had figured them out. The ones that might elude humanity for centuries or forever. We don't shy away from any questions on the podcast, but we seek to approach them and explain our knowledge and our ignorance to you. My friend and co host Jorge is on a break, but I have a special tree for you Today. We are very lucky to have as a guest one of my favorite physicists and one of my favorite writers about physics. Today we'll be talking to Professor Sean Carroll about some of the problems at the heart of quantum mechanics and a potential solution. So today on the podcast, we'll be answering the question what is the many world's interpretation of quantum mechanics? So it's my great pleasure to introduce Professor Sean Carroll. He's a theoretical physicist at Caltech, and he's known for his work on cosmology, general relativity, and the foundations of quantum mechanics. He's also the author of several widely acclaimed and widely read books, including Something Deeply Hidden and The Big Picture, and is the host of the podcast Mindscape, which might actually be neardier than this podcast. Today, Sean is here to talk to us about the many world's interpretation of quantum mechanics and the measurement problem in quantum mechanics. Sean Welcome to the podcast.

Thanks very much for having me here.

Wonderful to have you. So I want to die ride in and before we talk about what the mini world's interpretation is, I want to get your view on what problem it solves, Like, why do we need so many interpretations of quantum mechanics? What problem is it that they are trying to address?

I think there's actually two problems. I mean, this is the right question, because are we just wasting our time or its Honestly, it's not a lot of time compared to other physicists thinking about other things. The foundations of quantum mechanics is a minority pursuit. But I think there are two problems, and they're such looming, large problems, and quantum mechanics is so important to modern physics that I do wish we were spending more time on them. So in quantum Mechanics, I'll try to give my briefest version of quantum mechanics that we can we talk about objects in the universe, whether it's an electron or whatever, in a different way than we talked about them in classical mechanics. And Isaac Newton's view of the universe and Newton's view, we would have a position a location in space for a particle, and we would also have a velocity. And if you knew the positions and velocities of everything in the universe, in principle, you could predict what would have happen, and you could measure what would happen as much as you want. In quantum mechanics, we say no, no, no, that's not how we describe reality. There's something called the wave function, which for a single particle like an electron, is just very wave like basically at every point in space that has a value. But positions and velocities are not properties of the electron anymore. There are things we can observe about it, and the wave function tells us the probability that we'll get different answers if we observe like the position or the momentum. The momentum is just the mass times the velocity. So this raises two big questions. One is what is the wave function? Is it supposed to be the real world? Is it that somehow we're not measuring the real world exactly when we do our measurements, But it really is described by this weird thing called the wave function that we don't have direct access to. Or is it just part of the world, And there's other extra variables in addition to the wave function, hidden variables sometimes called them. Or does the wave function have nothing to do with the real world and it's just a way of predicting the experimental outcomes and the real world is something much more definite than that. So all three of these options are very much on the table. This is what I call the reality problem, like what is the real world? Is it the wave function or something weirder, something else, I should say, not necessarily weirder. The other problem with that brief version of quantum mechanics I just gave you is that it involves the word measure or observe. Right, No other fundamental theory of physics uses those words at all. They just assume that you can measure whatever you want. But in quantum mechanics it seems to be the case that you need separate rules for describing systems when you're not measuring them and describing them when you are measuring them. And so this raises what we call the measurement problem, which is what's up with that? Which includes like, what do you mean measured? Is it you know what is the definition do measurement is? It does need to be a conscious creature? Could it be a robot or a video camera? What if you just measure it badly? Does the same thing happen? When does it happen? How quickly does it happen? Why is there even a separate set of rules. So a whole bunch of questions get swept under the rug of the measurement problem in quantum mechanics. And I think both these are really big problems. If we want to think the quantum mechanics is the right theory of how reality works, we need to know what reality is, and we need to know why this measurement process plays such a special role.

And you make a really interesting distinction there. You say, an electron, we can observe these properties of it, or we can observe these quantities, but it no longer has these properties that its velocity's position are not like aspects of the electron. You've separated the electron from these things we can learn about it.

Yeah, And actually, in doing that, I've already cheated. I've already sort of slipped into my favorite way of thinking about quantum mechanics. Because there are people who would say that the wave function is just a way to predict the outcomes of what do you measure? And there really is something called the position, something called the velocity, we just don't know how how to predict what it's going to be until we measure them. Whereas someone like myself is a wave function realist, my point of view is, look, every version of quantum mechanics uses something like the wave function. Okay, either the wave function or something completely equivalent to it. So the simplest, most minimal version of quantum mechanics would only use the wave function, right, Like, not as a route to get to somewhere else or as part of the story, but the whole story, Like why not imagine that the wave function is actually what the world is? And when that's true in that perspective, it becomes the case that things like positions and velocities are not features of the wave function, they are possible experimental outcomes. And that's the biggest conceptual hurdle here, because we all look at things and we think they have positions, and we think they have velocities. And if you're this wave function realist kind of version of quantum mechanics, no longer. Is that true?

So let's move from positions and velocities to something that's more binary, because I think it's easier to think about Let's talk about the electric on and it's spin like, maybe it's spin up or maybe it's spin down. So then what's the problem with the orthodox the Copenhagen approach to quantum mechanics where you say, I have a wave function that describes the probabilities of this election on being spin up or spin down, and then when I make a measurement, when I poke it with my finger, the universe rolls to die and says, okay, well you had a sixty percent chance of being spin up, so you got spin up or nope, you got spin down this time. What's the problem with taking that approach?

Well, you already said when I measure the spin or when I poke it, I want something more definite than that. If what I'm talking about here is a really fundamental theory of physics, I should not be able to rely on weasel words about poking and measuring, or at least I should give a super duper rigorous definition of what exactly that is. And the originators of quantum mechanics and its conventional textbook form, the Copenhagen interpretation resolutely refused to do this. The strategy they adopted was to say that observe like you and me just aren't subject to the rules of quantum mechanics. We are classical. We are as if quantum mechanics never happened. Okay, you and I, and this is perfectly compatible with our everyday experience of the world. But then they say, but individual particles are atoms obey the rules of quantum mechanics. And you come along and say, well, but I'm made of atoms. How can it be if my atoms obey quantum mechanics and I obey classical mechanics. And so the real problem with this sort of conventional textbook version of quantum mechanics is that it's just not a definite physical theory. It's not even something you can compare to other things. It assumes that we're in a regime where this division between quantum and classical is good enough to get us by. And I think that when it comes to fundamental physics we need to do better than that.

And for example, if I'm poking something with my finger, you could say, well, I'm classical, so it should collapse the wave function. But then you can imagine the very very tip of my finger is just a quantum particle, and that shouldn't collapse the wave function. And so at what point is that function collapsing happening? Is it two layers of quantum particles? Is it ten? Is it when it getst a my neuron? As you said, there's no good answer to that.

Yeah, exactly right. And you know, what if you miss the particle or what if you like grades it? You know, all of these questions you can ask are just you're told you're not allowed to ask them in the conventional way of thinking about quantum mechanics.

Well, I mean I am a professional particle physicist. I think I know how to poke a particle when I want to, But I won't take umbridge at your example. So then what is the solution offered by the many world interpretation? How does that solve this problem?

So many worlds came about from a graduate student, Hugh Everett. So this is always what you should aspire to do as a graduate student, overthrow the fundamental nature of reality. And interestingly, Everett was working with John Wheeler, who was a very famous physicist who was an acolyte of Neils Bohr, the grandfather of the Copenhagen interpretation, and Wheeler gave him the following thesis problem quantize gravity. This turns out to be very hard quantizing gravity. We use the word quantized as a verb to turn an existing classical theory into a quantum theory. And what happens with gravity gravity we understand classically pretty well in a theory called general relativity given to us by Einstein. And the point is the reason why it becomes a problem for quantum mechanics is both technical, like when you try to quantize gravity, run into infinities and other things you don't like, but there's also conceptual problems. Everett said, Look, in the Copenhagen view of quantum mechanics, it's crucial that I have the quantum system I'm looking at and the outside observer poking it. But if I'm quantizing the universe, then I don't have an outside observer. I have the whole universe. I should include all the possible observers in there. So he started thinking about that. He said, what happens if we just include the quantum state of observers as well, I don't know why it took twenty years for people to guess this, but he has a very natural place to go. What happens if you let the observer be part of the wave function rather than treating them differently. So consider that electron that we had where you could get either spin up or spin down, right, and consider the following possibility. Since you're a particle physicist, we're going to assume that you're pretty good at measuring the spin of the electron. And what that means is if the electron was absolutely one hundred percent spin up, we're going to grant you that you would always measure it to be spin up. So that means that you, as a physical system would evolve into a state where your brain says, I'm measured it spin up. And likewise for spin down, if the electron was one hundred percent spin down, we're going to grant you that you would say, yep, I measured that to be spinned down.

Now you're saying that I can do something which is unfamiliar to me, which is I can be in a quantum state. I can have a superposition of having measured one thing and the other thing.

Well, I haven't said that yet, I'm about to say that, but I was. What I was so far saying is if the electron was one hundred percent spin up and you measured it spin you would find it to be spin up. You're not a super position of anything, right, And likewise, if it's one hundred percent spin down, you'd be spinned down. Let's assume that. Let's assume we want to be getting the right answer when the answer is definite and known already. Okay, I mean that's the least that we can ask.

I'm a reliable measuring device so.

Far, Yeah, exactly. But then if you are a quantum system, that's all you need to know because quantum mechanics and the technical jargon, it's linear. So what that means is if the electron is definitely spin up, you always get spin up. If it's definitely spinned down, you always get spinned down. Then when it's in a combination, when it's in a superposition of both, we know what you're going to evolve into the wave function of you plus the electron will evolve into part of it where the electron is spin up and you measured it spin up, and a part where the electron is spinned down and you measured it spin down. So this is taking advantage of the quantum mechanical feature of entanglement that you don't separately say, well, here's the wave function for you, here's the way function for the electron, et cetera. There's only one wave function for everything. And in fact, Everet referred to his own theory not as many worlds, but as the theory of the universal wave function. And so everyone agrees with this. By the way, everyone agrees that if you treat you as a quantum system and you measure that spin, you evolve into an entangled superposition, part of which says the electron has spin up and that's what you saw. Likewise for spin down. Everett's only move is to say, and that's okay, there's nothing wrong with that. So the immediate visceral response is that can't be right, because I'd measured electrons before and I've never felt like I was in a superposition. And EVERYTT says, that's fine, because you've misidentified yourself in the wave function. You think that you're this combination of having measured spin up and having measured spin down. But that's not right because you're entangled with the electron. There's two parts of the wave function, one of which is very consistent. The electron has spin up, and you measure to be spin up. Other part is also very consistent, the electron has spinned down, and you measure to be spinned down. And Everett points out that in the future evolution of the wave function, these two parts of the wave function will never interfere or interact with each other. Ever, again, they have no influence on what each other are doing. If I poke, as you say, if I change or alter what's going on in part of the wave function where the spin was up, let's say, the part where spin is down doesn't know it is not influenced by that. So it is as if these two parts of the wave function are now describing separate worlds. And the crucial thing to keep in mind, whether or not you like many worlds, is that Everett didn't put in a bunch of worlds. All he said was that we're going to take wave functions seriously and include observers in them. The world's come along for free. Once you believe that the electron can be in a superposition of spin up and spin down, you've got to be able to believe that observers can be in the superposition of I measured spin up and I measured spin down.

I see. So he avoids this distinction between quantum observers which don't collapse the wave function, and classical observers, which do collapse it by saying everything is quantum. Nothing ever collapses the way function, that the wave function is the universe. It just keeps going, but you experience one outcome rather than the other because you are no longer every part of the wave function. You are part of the way function that experienced spin up, or you are part of the way function that experience spin down. Is that a fair summary?

That is precisely right. Actually, that's an excellent summary. So I think that if we're being fair, we should all agree on the pros and cons. At this point of view, the pro is it's just quantum mechanics already taken at face value. There's a wave function for everything. Like you said, everything is quantum, and it obeys one single equation, the Schrodinger equation or some equivalent version thereof. You don't need new variables, you don't need new dynamical laws, you don't need any extra stuff. So at the level of writing down the theory. It's the simp possible version of quantum mechanics, but of course the cons are at the level of coming to terms with it. It's the biggest possible imaginative leap, right because we're saying that every single time we measure the spin of an electron, a new world is created. And you know, you got to give the skeptics a fair nod to say, yeah, like, that's a lot to buy, and we proponents of it will say, but you already bought it when you bought quantum mechanics, Like you sneakily were already there. We're just putting your face in it.

Well, what do you think that moment was like for Everett when he you know, followed this line of thinking and then had this perhaps moment of understanding where he realizes, hold on a second, maybe the universe has all these different layers and is much vast or much more complex than we imagine. What was that moment? Like? Did he ever write about that, you know, moment of epiphany or or realization or understanding?

As far as I know, he didn't directly write about that, No, but he wrote a lot In fact, you know, Wheeler, who is his advisor, was trying to pretend Wheeler himself was in a superposition of Everett has done something radical and interesting, and Everett is just going along with the conventional Copenhagen interpretation. Because Wheeler didn't want to annoy his own mentor Neil's borr, so he had Everett both visit Copenhagen literally and you know bores people visit Princeton where they were living themselves. And letters went back and forth. But there is a lot of writing about this, and the one thing I will say is that you know, again, as working physicists, both of us, some physicists are just lucky. Sometimes right you're in the right place at the right time, you get either the right experimental data, you get the right idea, and good for you, and you get credit for that, but we do inevitably separate that out from how good you are, how smart you are, how brilliant you are. Right like, I mean, there's brilliant people who just never were in the right place at the right time, and there's some people got lucky. And if you didn't know any better, which I didn't when I first started thinking about this, Hugh Everett would be the class example of someone who got lucky right, someone who's just in the right place at the right time. He only had one idea. He left physics after graduate school and moved on to other things. But you read what he wrote about this stuff and you realize, oh, no, actually he was brilliant. He completely understood what he was doing. And this is what I mean by being brilliant, because very often, like someone will have an idea in theoretical physics, and someone else, super duper smart, will understand and appreciate the implications of that idea and spell it all out. And Ever did both. He really appreciated exactly what he was saying, and in these letters going back and forth to the giants of quantum mechanics back in Europe, Everett more than held his own. In fact, he kind of ran rings around him. So I don't know how he felt when he first came up with the idea, but I do give him credit for really thinking through the implications.

Of that idea. Wonderful. Well, I want to talk more about the implications of many worlds and what it means, but first let's take a quick break with big wireless providers. What you see is never what you get. Somewhere between the store and your first month's bill. The price, your thoughts you were paying magically skyrockets. With Mintmobile, You'll never have to worry about gotcha's ever again. When Mint Mobile says fifteen dollars a month for a three month plan, they really mean it. I've used Mintmobile and the call quality is always so crisp and so clear. I can recommend it to you. So say bye bye to your overpriced wireless plans, jaw dropping monthly bills and unexpected overages. You can use your own phone with any mint Mobile plan and bring your phone number along with your existing contacts. So dit your overpriced wireless with mint Mobiles deal and get three months a premium wireless service for fifteen bucks a month. To get this new customer offer and your new three month premium wireless plan for just fifteen bucks a month, go to mintmobile dot com slash universe. That's mintmobile dot com slash universe. Cut your wireless bill to fifteen bucks a month at mintmobile dot com slash universe. Forty five dollars upfront payment required equivalent to fifteen dollars per month. New customers on first three month plan only speeds slower about forty give bigbytes on unlimited plan. Additional taxis, fees and restrictions apply. Seement Mobile for details.

AI might be the most important new computer technology ever. It's storming every industry and literally billions of dollars are being invested, so buckle up. The problem is that AI needs a lot of speed and processing power. So how do you compete without cost spiraling out of control. It's time to upgrade to the next generation of the cloud. Oracle Cloud Infrastructure or OCI. OCI is a single platform for your infrastructure, database, application development, and AI needs. OCI has four to eight times the bandwidth of other clouds, offers one consistent price instead of variable regional pricing, and of course nobody does data better than Oracle. So now you can train your AI models at twice the speed and less than half the cost of other clouds. If you want to do more and spend less, like Uber eight by eight and Data Bricks Mosaic, take a free test drive of OCI at Oracle dot com slash strategic. That's Oracle dot com slash stritch Oracle dot com slash strategic.

If you love iPhone, you'll love Apple card It's the credit card designed for iPhone. It gives you unlimited daily cash back that can earn four point four zero percent annual percentage yield. When you open a high Yield savings account through Apple Card, apply for Apple Card in the wallet app subject to credit approval. Savings is available to Apple Card owners subject to eligibility. Apple Card and Savings by Goldman Sachs Bank USA, Salt Lake City Branch Member FDIC terms and more at applecard dot com. When you pop a piece of cheese into your mouth or enjoy a rich spoonful of Greek yogurt, you're probably not thinking about the environmental impact of each and every bite. But the people in the dairy industry are. US Dairy has set themselves some ambitious sustainability goals, including being greenhouse gas neutral by twenty fifty. That's why they're working hard every day to find new ways to reduce waste, conserve natural resources, and drive down greenhouse gas emissions. Take water, for example, most dairy farms reuse water up to four times. The same water cools the milk, cleans equipment, washes the barn, and irrigates the crops. How is US Dairy tackling greenhouse gases. Many farms use anaerobic digestors that turn the methane from maneuver into renewable energy that can power farms, towns, and electric cars. So the next time you grab a slice of pizza or lick an ice cream cone, know that dairy farmers and processors around the country are using the latest practices and innovations to provide the nutrient dense dairy products we love with less of an impact. Visit usdairy dot com slash sustainability to learn more. All right, we're back and we are talking about the mind blowing idea that maybe the universe is more than just what we see, That there are many universes out there, part of this quantum multiverse where the universe is constantly splitting based on the various possibilities of what could happen every time quantum particles interact. And I think that the question that probably most listeners have is probably a you hear a lot, is are these other worlds real? In what sense? Are they real?

Like?

Is this a calculational tool to help us understand our experience or are those worlds like in some sense really out there?

Yeah? I think they're real. You know, this gets into deep philosophical questions about what you mean by real right away. But you know, here's how I think about it. If we have our best explanation for what we observe, and that explanation takes the form of some physical theory, and that physical theory predicts the existence of stuff we don't observe, then we take that stuff seriously until we have a better physical theory. Right. So, I mean, we often discover new things in the universe by doing this, whether it's you know, new planets or dark matter or whatever. And so if you take Everett's version of quantum mechanics seriously, he solves the both the reality problem and the measurement problem. The answer to the reality problem is the wave function directly describes reality. The answer to the measurement problem is when a quantum mechanical system becomes entangled with big, microscopic things, that's what counts as a measurement. And a prediction of his resolution to these two problems is that these other worlds are real. So if you want to get the benefit of his solutions, but you find the other worlds distasteful, that's okay. But then you have to come up with a better theory, and you have to come up with a disappearing world's theory where you get rid of the other worlds, and you can do that. People have done that. I mean, I'm saying it in a sort of facetious voice, but it is in fact an ongoing research program to do exactly that. And the problem is there's a couple of problems. One is it is inevitably more complicated, right, I mean, you're adding something to a very clean, crisp formalism to get rid of parts of it that you find distasteful. And number two, it's hard to make it work. Everett is very plug and play, and especially when you go from a quantum mechanical theory of particles to a theory of fields and then to a theory of quantum gravity, which was his initial motivation ever ready in quantum mechanics, is perfectly happy doing any one of those. Whereas when you try to mess with it adding more variables or adding more rules or whatever, you kind of find you have to mess with it in different ways for every version of the theory, and who knows what will end up being so both from a philosophical point of view, and I think from a physicist point of view, the simplicity and success of the evert interpretation speaks to not working so hard to get rid of the other worlds.

So I think that you're responding to sort of implied criticism in my question, which is about the nature of what is real, which is totally reasonable. And you know, I think that a lot of people argue that if you can't measure it directly, if you can't interact with it, then it's not real physically, that it can only be real philosophically. And I think that your response is probably if it's required by your theory, and your theory is the only one you have that describes what you can observe, then what's required by your theory but not observed is still real. Is that fair?

Yeah, I think that's exactly right. And honestly, if all you wanted to do was to say, I believe everything that Everett says, but I don't believe the other worlds are real, you know, knock yourself out. It's a free country, right, Like, I don't know what you get from that. I think if you face up to that perspective, you're going to have to change the physics. You're gonna have to change the equations to literally get rid of those other worlds, and you're going to get in trouble doing that. But if it's just kind of an attitude like I don't care about the other worlds because I'm not in them, then that's fine. Whatever. I do think. You know, one thing just to put on the table that maybe we'll get back to later, is that it's not just philosophy. You know, I really do think that one of the reasons why we still struggle to understand quantum gravity, for example, as a field of theoretical physics, is exactly because we have not struggled hard enough to understand quantum mechanics. And I think that rather than sort of putting the heads in the sand and denying the existence of these other worlds, if you do take the formalism seriously, it provides new angles of fruitful approach to longstanding problems in physics. So you know, it's a reason to not give in to your first impulse to be worried about all those other worlds.

Well, we were chatting with Carlo Ravelli a few weeks ago, and he said that every interpretation of quantum mechanics has a cost, and I think that a lot of people would see, you know, these infinite other universes as maybe like a cost of the many worlds interpretation. But to me, it's exactly what I got into physics to do, is to blow my mind and shake up my intuition about the universe. I don't get into physics to have the universe say yeah, Daniel, what you thought about the universe? That's basically it. I'm hoping to peel back a layer of reality and see something shocking, which at first is difficult to accept because it's different from my intuition, but that eventually, guided by mathematics, I can help some new intuition be like, Wow, the universe is different from what I imagined, and it works in this incredibly beautiful way. So to me, it's not a cost, it's a feature. It's the goal of digging to quantum mechanics. But my question is, you just said that we've been hesitant to dig into the foundations of quantum mechanics. Why do you think that is? Why do you think that for such an important problem at the core of modern physics, that progress has been so slow. Why haven't we taken this question more seriously.

I think it's a large number of reasons. And this is a very very good question also that I've talked about other people have talked about. But it's sort of a more sociology psychology history question, right, So it's a little on shakier ground here, so forgive me. But you know, part of it is just that we don't know how to answer it. That if there are different competing versions of quantum mechanics that are well defined physical theories, so you know, pilot wave theories and I guess Carlo's relational quantum mechanics, et cetera. There are various spontaneous collapse models on the market, and these are real physical theories. The problem with Copenhagen this is not a real physical theory. It just doesn't answer certain questions about what actually happens. But once you like put on your big boy pants and actually make a theory, then you can make addictions with that theory and you can try to experimentally test them. So I think that for a long time it was just thought to be not very fruitful to think about these ideas because we didn't know how to get any experimental data about them, and the other aspect is, you know, we had other things going on. Businesses are very good at, you know, pushing forward in directions they can make progress on. So we're talking about the thirties, forties, fifties, right, Like, there were particles in nuclei to understand, There were bombs to build, there were superconductors to construct, and quantum field theories to invent and renormal and you know it goes on and on, right, So there's plenty of work to do that you could connects directly to experimental progress. So it was kind of okay to push the foundations of quantum mechanics into the background.

That's sort of like saying, you know, my debit card still works, so I don't need to check my balance because probably everything is fine.

That's right. I mean, that is part of it. But also, you know, it's very common advice when you have an enormous task in front of you to first do the parts you can do, rather than fretting about the parts you can't do. I think that what has changed recently is number one, technology has grown to the point where this idea of a division between the classical world and the quantum world as part of the fundamental description of reality has just become increasingly untenable. Right, we can make much larger quantum systems than we could back in the thirties that are in superpositions, and we need to deal with the reality of entanglement and so forth when we build quantum computers and things like that. And the other is that this enormous progress we made on understanding particle physics and field theory has slowed in the past few decades, and we're in this weird position where we built these amazingly successful theories that fit all the data, but we know they're not the final answer, right because gravity is not included, because there are these naturalness problems, et cetera, et cetera. So one strategy is just to stubbornly bull forward new using these same tools we've used before. But another strategy is to take a step back and Okay, maybe we have to think fundamentally in a different way about these questions to make progress on them, and thinking about the foundations of quantum mechanics plays into that strategy.

So I guess it's time to check the balance, huh. And we got to figure out what's happening down there.

In the base we keep getting turned down at the ATM.

So yeah, so then digging deep into what it means this many world's interpretation, the many worlds interpretation says essentially that none of these universes are special or different that these branching aspects of the wave function, and it sort of avoids the collapse question that way. But I can't get around what you said earlier, which is that you're redefining what it means to be me right, because this universe does feel special to me. I mean, I'm in this one. It's the only one that I can interact with. Is that sort of a naive objection to the many world's interpretations to say that this one must somehow be different? Can you swap that away by just saying, well, the other Daniels also think that they're the only one who interacts with the universe.

Pretty much. Yes, that's exactly how I will slipe it away. The relevant anecdote here that writings love this anecdote, so I will just share it. It is actually about Ludwig Wickenstein, the philosopher, So one day one of his former students, Elizabeth Anscomb, was also an extremely accomplished philosopher in her own right. She comes across Witckenstein, you know, standing in the yard at Cambridge like looking at the sun. And Levickenstein was famously a little idiosyncratic. So she says, what is going on? And he says, you know, why is it the people were reluctant to believe that the earth rotated rather than believing that the sun moved around the earth. And Anscomb says, well, it just looks like the sun moves around the earth, right, And Vickenstein says, well, what would it have looked like if the earth rotated? So the point being that the question you should be asking is not start with an impression I see the Sun moving and then construct a theory that fits most closely with that immediate impression. The strategy should be construct theories and then ask what observers within those theories would observe, and if it's consistent with what we observe, then it works. So the point is that in many worlds, if there's you right here and then you go and do some experiments, that's cern and you observe some particles, the prediction is there are now many, many branches in which the specific pattern of particles in a collision are different in every single branch, and the version of you has now seen different things, and all of those versions of you exist, and they've seen different things, and they all think that they're special because they exist, and the other ones are kind of dubious. But there's no pointer that says this is the real, real one, right. There are other versions of quantum mechanics that try to do that, to try to say like, this is the real branch and all the other ones are fake, but it would still be true we without that pointer that says this one is real, that all of the different versions of you on the different branches would feel equally real. So the experimental empirical prediction of this theory is exactly what we observe in the world, and I think that should be the criterion for saying whether or not it's an adequate explanation.

It is interesting. It does feel somehow like a bit of sleight of hand, like you've taken the fuzziness of defining a classical object in terms of quantum mechanical particles and you sort of transformed it into like, well, I'm just going to redefine what you are, you aren't who you thought you were. You're just an element of this quantum wave function instead of being like the holistic version of you. It feels to me like, you know, when you make this step you have this interpretation of quantum mechanics, you need to say, one, what the wave function is. It's real, it's the universe, but also something about like the correspondence between the quantum state of the universe and your experience of it as an observer.

Yeah, no, that's one hundred percent true. And so again, if we're honest about the pros and cons, the physics of ever writing quantum mechanics is as simple as it can be, but the philosophy requires some new moves. And I'm one hundred percent, you know, on board with people who say I just can't accept those moves, like it's too much, or at least say it this way. You know, if we think we don't agree on what the correct version of quantum mechanics is, and each of us has our credence for saying, well, it's probably this, but unlikely that it's perfectly fair for one of the ingredients that goes into your choice of your personal credence to say this redefinition of who I am is just so dramatic that I'm going to be skeptical of it. Maybe it's true, but I'm going to be a little dubious until I'm forced into it. I think that's okay. And so I think that this I'm completely acknowledging that the philosophical leaps required by many worlds are substantial, and in other versions they're just not there. They don't bother me as much. Like you know, I think that in physics we very often come across better understandings of the world, including of ourselves. Right Like we might have thought back in the day that we were a spirit animating a fleshy machine that housed us, and now we think otherwise. I think that's okay. As long as again, as long as the model that we're building, once we understand it turns out to be completely compatible with the world we observe, then I'm on board.

Well, then let's talk about how to use many world's interpretation as a functioning theory of quantum mechanics, because something that is a bit slippery for me is that in the Cope Taca interpretation, I know what a probability means. I'm going to do an experiment, and I'm either going to get spin up or spin down. I can look at the way of function. I can say, well, project it, you know, against both of these possible outcomes, and those give me the probabilities that just use the Born rule, and whether or not I'm a quantum or classical observer is sort of separate from that. But in many worlds, everything happens, and so I can no longer say like, well, the probability of this happening is forty percent or sixty percent, because they both happen in some universe. How do you define probability if everything that can happen is going to happen.

Yeah, I think this is the right question to ask. Like I said, there are objections to many worlds that are not very good objections that are just misunderstandings. But there are also puzzle or problems or things we got to address that arise only in many worlds that weren't there before. So you know, I gave Everett credit for solving the reality problem and the measurement problem, an equal number of new problems arise. And the reason why I think that's okay is because I can see the solutions for these problems pretty clearly, even if we don't have them completely spelled out. One problem is just and maybe we'll get to this if you want to, but it's the structure problem, which is why does the world look so classical to us if it's really this big quantum wave function and there's a lot of details in that. And the other one, like you said, is the probability problem. The benefit of effort is that the underlying equations are lean and mean and austere, so there's no room to say, okay, the wave function evolves, and there's a rule that says the probability for getting a measurement is given by the wave function square, like, there's no room to add extra rules like that. So what you need to do is derive these rules, and there are different strategies for doing it. And to be clear, the fact that the probability is given by the wave functions squared rather than just by the wave function or by the wave function cube, the logarithm or whatever, that's not the problem. Of course, It's going to be given by the wave function squared because the set of numbers which are given by the wave function squared are the unique set of numbers that are all non negative and they add up to one, and they're conserved over time. That's what you want out of a probability. And it's just Pythagoras's theorem, right. The hyplot new squared is the other two sides squared. That's why you take all of the different amplitudes in the wave function squared, add them up and get one. So that's not the tricky part. The tricky part is, like you said, why are their probabilities at all? Because it's a completely deterministic theory and different people have their angles on that. I think that I've solved it along with my collaborator Chip Sabans, because well, we borrowed an idea from someone else. I should give credit to who's lev Vidmin. But here's the idea. When you measure that spin, so there's some amplitude saying the spin is up, there's some amplitudes saying the spin is down. And you measure, and like you say, with probability one, there is now a version of you on the branch where the spin was up, in a version of you that is on the branch where the spin is down. But if you be a good physicist and you do all the details carefully, you can say, well, you know, ever, it purportedly explains to me when these measurement occurs. It's just an entanglement process. I can calculate when it happens, And the answer is, it happens incredibly quickly. The timescale for the branching to happen is shorter than the lifetime of the Higgs boson for those particle physicists out there right like less than ten of the mine is twenty seconds, and so your brain doesn't work that fast. You can't actually know which branch you're on as quickly as the branching happens. So what that means is, inevitably, when the wave function does branch, there's a period of time when there are two copies of you who those the world is not identical, but those copies of you are identical, okay, And neither one of those knows what's branch it's on. So even if it knows the entire wave function of the universe, there is something about itself that neither one of those copies of you knows, namely which branch it's on. This is called self locating uncertainty or indexical uncertainty. And in those cases, you know there's some fact about the world, but you don't know it. What do you do as a good Bayzian reasoner, as a good modern rational person. You assign credences. You assign non negative numbers that add up to one, right, that act like probabilities. So it's a subjective probability. I don't know which branch I'm on, but I'm going to sign a credence. And you might say, well, what do I care about the wave function? I'm just going to assign credences that are fifty to fifty, right, because there's two options, I'm going to sign equal credence. Turns out that doesn't work. It's inconsistent because you can then branch the wave function again. Depending on whether the spin was up or spin was down, you have a different number of branches, and now you have to assign like one third, one third, one third. So the first guy's probability changes even though nothing happened in his world. So that's kind of inconsistent over time, assigning the born rule probabilities, giving the probability the credence. The subjective probability assigned by the wave functions squared is the uniquely consistent thing you can do in this situation. So number one, there are inevitably uncertainties, and number two, the uniquely rational way to assign credences to them is the Born rule.

So then the uncertainties reflect more like our ignorance rather than some fundamental property of the universe.

That's right, And people like me would go so far as to say, that's always what you mean by probability. I mean, there's something that happens in the world but we don't know, so we assign different credances to it. It's a subjectivist basian version of probability.

I see. So then does many world's interpretation require basian probability or rule out frequency is probability?

It certainly comports way more comfortably with basian notions of probability. So you don't need to be as extremist as I am and think that all probabilities are fundamentally subjective to be an Averreadian. But it doesn't hurt. It helps you sleep better at night. Let's put it that way.

Let's take a quick brick. When you pop a piece of cheese into your mouth, or enjoy a rich spoonful of Greek yogurt. You're probably not thinking about the environmental impact of each and every bite, but the people in the dairy industry are. US Dairy has set themselves some ambitious sustainability goals, including being greenhouse gas neutral by twenty to fifty That's why they're working hard every day to find new ways to reduce waste, conserve natural resources, and drive down greenhouse gas emissions. Take water, for example, most dairy farms reuse water up to four times the same water cools the milk, cleans equipment, washes the barn, and irrigates the crops. How is US Dairy tackling greenhouse gases. Many farms use anaerobic digestors that turn the methane from maneuver into renewable energy that can power farms, towns, and electric cars. So the next time you grab a slice of pizza or lick an ice cream cone, know that dairy farmers and processors around the country are using the latest practices and innovations to provide the nutrient dense dairy products we love with less of an impact. Visit us dairy dot com slash sustainability to learn more.

Our iHeartRadio Music Festival presented by Capital One coming back to Las Vegas two nights September twenty first on one stage, stream live only on a weekend full of superstar performances, never seen before, collaborations, and once in a lifetime artist moments you'll have to see to believe. Tickets are on sale now at axcess dot Com. Don't miss Asap Rocky Big, Shuan, Camilakable Dulipa, When Stefani has Hoosier Scree, Thurban, New Kids on the Block, Paramore, Chabouzie, The Black Crows.

The Weekend, Thomas Rhett, Victoria Monet, a special performance by Coldplays, Chris Martin and more. OK, you're seeking s to be there now at.

Axcess dot com.

Guess what, Mango?

What's that?

Will?

So iHeart is giving us a whole minute to promote our podcast, Part time Genius.

I know That's why I spent my whole week composing a high kup for the occasion. It's about my emotional journey in podcasting over the last seven years, and it's called Earthquake House.

Mega Mango, I'm going to cut you off right there.

Why don't we just tell people.

About our show instead?

Yeah, that's a better idea.

So every week on Part Time Genius, we feed our curiosity by answering the world's most important questions, things like when did America start dialing nine to one? One? Is William Shatner's best acting work in Esperanto?

Also?

What Happened to Esperanto? Plus we cover.

Questions like how Chinese is your Chinese food? How do dollar stores stay in business? And of course is there an Illuminati of cheese?

There absolutely is, and we are risking our lives by talking about it. But if you love mind blowing facts, incredible history and really bad jokes, make your brain happy and tune into Part Time Genius.

Listen to Part Time Genius on the iHeartRadio app or wherever you get your podcasts.

Hi everyone, it's me Katie Kuric. If you follow me on social media, you know I love to cook, or at least try, especially alongside some of my favorite chefs and foodies like Benny Blanco, Jake Cohen, Lighty Hoyke, Alison Roman, and of course Ininagarten and Martha Stewart. So I started a free newsletter called Good Taste that comes out every Thursday, and it's serving up recipes that will make your mouth water. Think a candied bacon, bloody mary tacos with cabbage slaw, curry cauliflower with almonds and mint, and cherry slab pie with vanilla ice cream to top it all off. I mean, young, I'm getting hungry. But if you're not sold yet, we also have kitchen tips like a full proof way to grill the perfect burger and must have products like the best cast iron skillet. To feel like a chef in your own kitchen, all you need to do is sign up at Katiecuric dot com slash good Taste. That's k A T I E C O U r C dot com slash good taste. I promise your taste buds will be happy you did.

And so then are these sort of like philosophical explorations the only way that we can make progress on these questions of the quantum foundations? I mean, if we have two interpretations of quantum mechanics, many worlds and relational for example, and they both are you know, actual physical theories unlike Copenhagen, and they both describe everything that we see as observers, then are we just forced to make philosophical choices between them? You know, as as individuals. Are there no experiments we can do to help us resolve this question?

Well, I think there's two answers to that. One one is that sometimes there are experiments that help us distinguish between them. You know, Roger Penrose has been pushing an idea where there are objective collapses of the wave function, where the wave function violates the Schrodinger equation and really does collapse other people. There's a famous theory called the GRW theory Girardi, Ramini and Weber who have a similar theory with different equations attached to it. And these are experimentally testable and tests are going on, right, so we're actually doing them. Theories like hidden variable theories Bomian mechanics, I think they should be experimentally distinguishable from averlready in quantum mechanics, But the proponents of those theories say they're not. So I'm a little suspicious about that. But I haven't actually, I can't put a good proposal on the table for how to experimentally distinguish them. But I still don't quite believe the standard lore in that case. For things like Ravelli's relational quantum mechanics, I don't understand it well enough to say I suspect that it will turn out to be fundamentally equivalent to one of the other approaches. Either it's just the wave function and it's evert with the many worlds, or there's got to be some hidden variables, or its epistemic. I think it's closest to what we call epistemic approach. Epistemic approaches, I haven't even mentioned those yet. Those are the ones where they really say, the wave function is just not reality, okay. In Penrose's approach or GRW or hidden variables, the wave function is part of reality, but its dynamics are a little bit different than in everet, whereas in a truly epistemic approach, the wave function is just a calculational tool and reality is something very, very different. And that's fine, But then what is reality? And I'm pretty sure, at least my strong belief from the current state of the answers people give me when I ask them, there's no good theory of what reality actually is in these models. And you know, they're like, wait till later, we'll figure that out. And in principle that's okay. You know, we can't ask that every theory has answer every question as soon as it's invented. But it's also perfectly fair to be skeptical of those theories while those questions still linger out there. But okay, but the other answer to your question, sorry that it has taken me so long to get to it is the proof of the pudding is in the tasting. And if I can make progress on other puzzles and physics by starting from an everready in perspective and taking it seriously, whereas my friends who are being epistemic or hidden variably or whatever don't make that progress, then by the rules of physics, I win, and vice versa. Right, if the people who are fundamentally hit pilot wave theories or epistemic people make progress that I don't, then they win. That's perfectly fair. So in this situation where we're not sure what the right answer is, then by all means, let people do the research in their favorite areas, and you know, whoever actually discovers something interesting will get the credit.

I like this idea of measuring competing theories by how much progress you can make, sort of theoretically or philosophically, to show that it's like, you know, a functioning, working fertile intellectual playground. But you raised this interesting question of you know what reality is? And I want to come back to something you mentioned earlier, which is why the universe if it is quantum, If the universe is a wave function and there's quantum particles and everything's governed by the shooting equation, and why doesn't feel that way to us?

You know?

Why we have this emergent experience which is so drastically not quantum. Is that something we can ever grapple with? Or is it just like other emergent phenomena, like asking like why is there ice cream at some points in the universe and not other points?

I think there's actually again two aspects of this. There's a sort of the philosophical aspect and the physical aspect. The philosophical aspect I don't have much to say about, which is just in a world like ours, Why is it that the idea of a self, the idea of an agent, the idea of a conscious creature is attached to just one branch of the wave function at a time. I already mentioned the fact that you know, fundamentally the different branches don't interact with each other. So if you tried to say, well, I'm going to treat reality to me as two of the branches, not any of the others. We ignore the others, are going to take these two well, I think that someone would say, yeah, but you have two things that have literally no impact on each other. The analogy I use in my book is what if there were a ghost world. What if there's a world that was sort of, you know, the same shape as the Earth and in the same physical location as the Earth in space, and there were people on it, and they talk to each other, but there was zero interaction through any force of nature or any other kind of influence between us and the people on ghost world. It just doesn't make sense to call them part of the same reality, right, I mean, there are two worlds for all times and purposes, certainly. So that's the sort of philosophical move I think that we don't have, or at least I'm not aware of a once and for all definition of what a world is and how you should divide up reality in that way. But that's the rough idea. You know, a set of things that interact with each other is a world. But the other interesting question is, you know I started that by saying in a world like ours, with laws of physics like ours. But okay, what are the features of our laws of physics that allow for each individual branch of the wave function to be mostly classical? You were pretty good at predicting the positions of planets in this guy and eclipses and so forth using Newtonian mechanics long before quantum mechanics came on the scene, right, So why is classical mechanics a good limit of quantum mechanics, especially given that you're saying there's all these other worlds out there, right? And that's a trickier question, And I think that we're just beginning to make progress on it. And the answer has things to do with ideas like entanglement and decoherence and locality. But fundamentally, you know, that's still a research level problem.

Well, I hope that we make some progress on it in the future. Now, I want to take a slight turn and ask you a little bit more of a personal question. You mentioned earlier that not only are you talking out there in the public about science, but you're actually a practicing physicist. And you know, in my experience, most people take one of two paths. They're either a practicing scientist or they are a science communicator. You know, I don't know that for example, Bill Nye or Neil deGrasse Tyson is still publishing papers. But you have kept your feet in both worlds. Has it been a challenge for you to remain part of the SIENIENTIVI community and maintain that credibility while also being a public intellectual.

Yeah, there's sort of two aspects to the challenge. One is, it's a lot of work do all these things to write papers and to advise grad students while also having a podcast and writing books and so forth. But you know what, look to be honest, it's not that much work, and I can compartmentalize it pretty easily, and it's fun for me, Like I get to do these things that all are individually very fun, and my personality is such that I like being able to switch gears and do different things at different times. I would get frustrated if I did the same exact kind of thing every day, so this is a good way to do that. The other aspect of the challenge is, like you say the word credibility, like what about how other people think of you? And yeah, that's absolutely a challenge because of course two things. Number one, public outreach and communication is itself undervalued and or devalued depending on who you're talking to, Like it's considered to be a waste of good brain CPU cycles that you could be using doing research, right, and doing research is what really matters. And number two, like you also imply, there's this idea that even if you think that outreach and communication are valuable, it's very difficult to imagine being productive in both spheres of both doing research and doing those kinds of things. There are famous counter examples Carl Sagan, Stephen Hawking, et cetera, Stephen Weinberg right, who recently passed away, but they're so rare that people almost don't take them seriously. And especially like there's the feeling that you should first become a super successful researcher and then you'd be allowed to do a little bit of writing books and things like that. I mean, Stephen Hawking invented black hole radiation long before he wrote A Brief History of Time and so forth. And Carl Sagan, on the other hand, never got elected to the National Academy of Sciences because people thought that he spent too much time doing outreach work. So that's a challenge, but you know, I'm too old to worry about that these days. It has impacted my career in very tangible, definite ways, but I'm still having fun doing what I want to do. So there you go.

Well, that's great to hear my experience a little bit of that. Also, when I talk to people in my card carrying particle physics world and they ask me, oh, you still doing research now that you're doing outreach, and so have to remind them it's possible to do more than the one thing.

So it's interesting. Let me just put it this way because I like this analogy. Physicists are not so narrow minded that they won't allow their colleagues to do anything else. Like if you are a ski jumper or a professional unicyclist or whatever, or not professional but amateur unicyclist in your spare time, other physicists would think, oh, that's cookie and fun. Good for you, and you're probably also still doing research. But there's something about writing books and giving talks and making videos and so forth that is different than writing unicycle or being a ski jumper, because that's the kind of thing that people think, well, you should be using that effort doing research, right, Like you're unicycling is just a different kind of thing, so we don't that takes away from your research. An enormous number of professional physicists are rock climbers and mountain climbers, right. You probably know many yourself, for example. That's fine. But if instead of going rock climbing you write a book, that's actually counts against you and that it's just a weird thing in my mind. But it's a very definite syndrome.

That is strange. And you know, this is it's interesting to explore these career paths, and I wonder is this sort of the path you envision for yourself. Like if you could go back in time and describe your life now to fresh faced assistant professor Sean Carroll one year into your gig at University of Chicago, how do you think that Sean would react?

Well, the specific twists and turns of my career were not what I predicted or wanted, but the ending point is pretty close. You know, I always wanted to be a broader intellectual contributor than just a narrow research physicist that you know, since I was a kid, I wanted that and that was always the plan in some sense, and I was charmingly naive about how happy academia would be to receive such a plan, But it was always a plan. And I do believe that the right way to do that is to first become an expert at something, Right Like, you don't start out as an expert in everything you know. You better get good at your research and your PhD project and then sort of branch out after that. But you can't predict all of the ins and outs. But maybe I would have done things differently if I had crystal ball and could predict the future. A few tweaks here and there, it would have helped. But you know, I think I can still hold my head high about the choices that I made along the way.

Well, what advice would you give to young folks now who are excited about science communication? In my experience, also, I followed a fairly narrow path and got tenure as an experimental particle physicists before trying to branch out to outreach other types of things. But I see graduate students in my own group doing outreach, and I wonder, you know, if I should advise them. Look, the field is not friendly to this kind of breath at this age, wait till you get tenure. If I'm telling them not to be their authentic intellectual selves, and I should encourage them and the field with it to grow and accept this kind of activity. What would be your advice or what is your advice to your students when they try to emulate the full breath of your activities.

It's enormously good and important question, and the answer is not obvious. But I can always fall back on the maxim that I should tell the truth. So I can tell the truth about factual statements about the world without necessarily coloring them by normative statements. So rather than saying don't do that until you get tenure, I can say, look, it's great that you like doing a lot of different things, al reach and so forth. I have one recent student of mine who is actually super duper successful hot property in the job market, wrote a musical and performed it you at cal Tech while he was in graduate school. So he did okay. But the point is that it's hard to become a professional academic right the numbers game is bad. I'm at cal Tech, and I tell my students that if you're at a place like cal Tech or Harvard or whatever, and you get a PhD, maybe one in four of you will eventually be tenured professors in that field. I don't know the exact numbers, and it will depend a lot on sub fields and where you get your pahd and so forth. But the numbers are against you, certainly. And the thing you can say with a good amount of confidence is that all else being fixed, doing outreachy things will lower the percentage chance that you will someday become tenured academic. Now, you might still decide to do it, and that's great, but I want you to go in with your eyes open, right, Like I sometimes get in trouble by being a little bit too candid with my students, because a lot of my colleagues are like now, they're young and impressionable. We have to like juice them up about physics. And I'm like, well, yeah, but a lot of them are not going to end up being physicists. And I think that I love the idea of going to grad school. I love the idea of getting a PhD. And I think it's intrinsically worthwhile thing. And I'm not going to discourage anyone from doing that. Because it's a matter of intellectual growth and so forth. I think the current system where you then have to do somewhere between five and ten years of post doc afterward is not ideal. But if you want to get a PhD, and I think that's the best thing in the world, and then you should know what the chances are and what the different aspects are that affect your chances along the way, and then you make your own decisions.

Well, I agree with that, and I hope that other folks out there can see that it's possible to be an academic and to do scientific communication and outreach, and that encourages the community to accept that and to broaden our concept of what a healthy physicist is. You're allowed to also be a unicycler or to talk about science to your friends and neighbors on the internet. All right, we've taken that for your time. Thanks very much for joining us and for telling us about your vision of quantum mechanics and explaining to us all the crazy, mind blowing ideas involved in the many world's interpretation. It's been a pleasure.

It's very fortunate that we have to think about these things. So thanks for having me on.

All right, Thanks very much, thanks for listening, and remember Daniel and Jorge Explain the Universe is a production of iHeartRadio. For more podcasts from iHeartRadio, visit the iHeartRadio Apple Apple Podcasts, or wherever you listen to your favorite shows. When you pop a piece of cheese into your mouth, you're probably not thinking about the environmental impact. But the people in the dairy industry are. That's why they're working hard every day to find new ways to reduce waste, conserve natural resources, and drive down greenhouse gas emissions. How is us dairy tackling greenhouse gases? Many farms use anaerobic digestors to turn the methane from manure into renewable energy that can power farms, towns, and electric cars. Visit you as dairy dot COM's Last sustainability to learn more.

Our iHeartRadio Music Festival for a sentate Ike Capital One Coming back to Las Vegas twenty first weekends all of Superstar performances as Rocky Bike, Shun Camilo, Ka, Veil to Uli, What's the Funny, Keith Herbit, New Kids on the Block, Paramore, Shaboozi, The Black Crows. The weekend Thmas Victoria Monette Old Plays, Chris Martin and more, Stream Live Polly on Hulu and get It gets to be there at axces dot com.

Guess what Will?

What's that Mango?

I've been trying to write a promo for our podcast, Part Time Genius, but even though we've done over two hundred and fifty episodes, we don't really talk about murderers or cults.

I mean, we did just cover the Illuminati of cheese, so I feel like that makes us pretty edgy. We also solve mysteries like how Chinese is your Chinese food? And how do dollar stores make money? And then of course can you game a dog show?

So what you're saying is everyone should be listening.

Listen to Part Time Genius on the iHeartRadio app or wherever you get your podcasts.

Daniel and Jorge Explain the Universe

A fun-filled discussion of the big, mind-blowing, unanswered questions about the Universe. In each e 
Social links
Follow podcast
Recent clips
Browse 637 clip(s)